1986
|
Factions: Something For Everyone
VIEWPOINT
By Karl Hess
Uniting only on the principle that force should not be initiated
to advance a cause, personal, political, or philosophical, members
of the Libertarian Party represent widely varying approaches to
social action.
The most radical of these approaches, and proudly described as
radical by those who follow it, is hard-line insistence that every
libertarian action should be an action directly and unambiguously
intended to abolish the nation state. The radical libertarian
position does not advocate any compromise, any middle-ground, any
realpolitik. It urges that the Libertarian Party place the
enunciation of principled anti-state arguments foremost. Campaigns
for elective office, in the radical view, serve as platforms for
the dissemination of radical views.
The radical view is contrasted sharply with the minarchist, or
minimum government viewpoint. The position here is that the Libertarian
Party, by calling itself a political party, should take "real world"
positions aiming at decreasing state power where it cannot abolish
it; in short, being political and practical in action even when
philosophical in discussion. Actually, to some minarchists, the
abolition of the state, root and branch, is not clearly desirable.
They hold to a notion of social agreement regarding governance which
sees a role for a public agency with at least the scope of a state
to protect property rights, reduce the cost of transactions, and,
perhaps, even defend the continent. Yet, if they have agreed to join
the Libertarian Party, they have also agreed that this arrangement of
governance would have to be accomplished without the initiation of
force.
A Libertarian Party member holding the radical view would not be likely
to campaign on an issue that sought to reduce the economic distortions
or garrison-state security measures of the Pentagon, but would prefer
to campaign on proposals to abolish the Pentagon altogether and
turn continental defense functions over to private military
corporations. The other Libertarian Party viewpoint would be to
campaign for immediately achievable revisions of existing security
laws.
From these two viewpoints, different political styles emerge.
The radical view is represented by Presidential campaigns waged on
precise and ideal statements of anti-state positions. The radical
style is abolitionist.
The minimum government view is represented by Presidential campaigns
waged with what are felt to be practical, achievable, and publicly
attractive legislative alternatives to existing policies. Further,
this viewpoint animates the actions of many Libertarian Party members
who have concentrated on local political campaigns even when they
involve only a limited opportunity to state the widest range of
libertarian positions. In this localist view, the privatization of
a single municipal service is useful even though it is not accomplished
in a campaign that seeks the abolition of all public service.
There is developing within the Libertarian Party another political
style that could be called one of synthesis. There are those who
hold strongly to the radical position as a matter of personal
conviction but who are willing to engage in practical political
activities, particularly at the local level, which do not or cannot
fully express those convictions. Their slogan might be "think
radically, act practically."
There will always, probably, be those in the Libertarian Party who
will stand only for an unalloyed radical or an unalloyed minimum
government position. Their arguments will constitute some of the most
exciting debates of Libertarian conferences and communication. And
those arguments will, as they are worked out, form the style of
specific Libertarian Party activities, such as Presidential campaigns.
The view of synthesis, meanwhile, may set the agenda for many local
campaigns beyond the fundamentist debates.
Beyond these positions held internally within the Libertarian Party
there are positions external to the Party but vital to the movement
toward individual responsibility and liberty.
There is the well-formed view that any political activity, even the
act of voting itself, is an endorsement of an over-arching nation
state political system which can only be described as coercive.
The fact that Libertarian Party members volitionally choose to engage
in politics as, one could say, an act of self-defense is not accepted
in the anti-party view. In the view of synthesis, the anti-party
view is treasured as an expression of liberty itself. All that is
asked is that anti-party energy -- although certainly not arguments --
concentrate its fire as fiercely on the nation state as on "heretical"
libertarians. The other side of that street, of course, is that Party
members (or partyarchs) follow the equivalent course.
Particularly challenging for members of the Libertarian Party is the
anti-party suggestion that any political activity strengthens the
nation state system and that the election of a Libertarian school
board member, for instance, although it might lead to new freedom
for private or home schooling locally, inexorably supports the
nationalized school system in the broader sense.
It is not the responsibility of critics to prove this. It is the
responsibility of Libertarian Party members to dis-prove it, and
it is an implied fundamental proposition of the Party position that
this can be done. It is the responsibility of Party members, also,
to come to grips with the problem presented by volunteering to
engage in the election of a hierarchical internal organization that
must always skate on the thin ice of possible bureaucratization.
Critics will be quick to point to the problems of such such an
organization, mimicking, as it does, many of the features of
traditional nation state institutions. Libertarian Party members,
rather than responding with anger to such criticism, again, might
respond with convincing proof that the spirit of liberty can survive
such an organized framework.
There is, also, the totally isolationist view that any action in the
public world is an invitation to mischief and to exposure to nation
state pressure. There is, of course, no conflict here with the
Libertarian Party since Party members choose voluntarily to ignore
the isolationist advice, at their own freely chosen risk. A slight
variation of the isolationist view is that carefully guarded
commercial activities, not colliding with great state power or
making claims on it, is the only proper activity for a libertarian.
There could hardly be a Libertarian Party position that would oppose
this. The Party's goal includes the eventual freedom for all humans
to engage in absolutely unfettered free market transactions. To those
who can achieve the goal already, in their personal dealings, all
libertarians must say hurray. There is, of course, nothing that bars,
in principle or practice, any Libertarian Party member from pursuing
their free market goals here and now as zealously as they are able.
Local practical political action, it is hoped, can advance that
freedom even though it may not be able to perfect it. Many hold the
same hope for Presidential-level activities.
The Libertarian Party, with factions within itself, is itself just
a faction of libertarianism generally. It is a faction of people
who have chosen, of their own free will, to engage in certain
political activities which they hold can have a positive effect on
the protection of or the spread of liberty. Every Libertarian Party
member should be grateful for the critical assaults launched against
it by other libertarians. It helps keep them on their toes. And where
that criticism proves unassailable and unanswerable then, in good
sense, Libertarian Party members should act upon it. Similarly, when
critical libertarians outside the Party find good work done by the
Party, they may wish to join, support, or at least acknowledge it.
There seem many paths toward liberty, whether those paths are called
factions or philosophies. We are each of us the means to our own ends.
Perhaps it is just the journey itself that beckons us all.
|